COHERENCEISMRESEARCH19TH & 20TH CENTURY EXISTENTIALISM

19th & 20th Century Existentialism

March 2, 2025
5 MIN READ
SECURE
OTHER RESOURCES

The Search for Authentic Existence: An Analysis of Existentialist Philosophy

Introduction

Existentialism emerged as a philosophical movement in the 19th and 20th centuries, focusing on the nature of human existence, freedom, responsibility, and the search for meaning in an apparently indifferent universe. Rather than representing a unified school of thought with a singular methodology, existentialism encompasses a diverse array of thinkers who, despite their methodological and conceptual differences, share a common concern with the fundamental condition of human existence. Central to existentialist thought is the notion that existence precedes essence—humans first exist and then, through their choices and actions, define who they are. Humans are thus condemned to freedom, burdened with the responsibility of creating meaning in a world that offers no predetermined values or purposes.

Existentialist philosophers grapple with questions about authenticity, anxiety, absurdity, and alienation, examining how individuals confront their finitude and contingency in a universe that seems indifferent to human concerns. The existentialist project is fundamentally concerned with how one might live authentically in full recognition of one's radical freedom and responsibility. This paper examines the distinctive contributions of six key thinkers whose work has shaped existentialist thought: Friedrich Nietzsche, Søren Kierkegaard, Arthur Schopenhauer, Martin Heidegger, Jean-Paul Sartre, and Albert Camus. Each philosopher approached the existentialist problematic from different angles, yet all were concerned with the fundamental question of how to create meaning in the face of apparent meaninglessness, how to respond to suffering, and how to live authentically.

By examining these thinkers' perspectives on the human condition, this analysis aims to provide a comprehensive understanding of existentialist philosophy and its enduring relevance in contemporary life. From Nietzsche's call to embrace life-affirming values to Camus's confrontation with the absurd, these philosophers offer profound insights into the nature of human existence and the possibilities for living meaningfully in an uncertain world.

Friedrich Nietzsche: The Will to Power and the Death of God

Friedrich Nietzsche (1844-1900) stands as one of the most provocative and influential precursors to existentialist thought, even though he never identified himself as an existentialist. His proclamation that "God is dead" in The Gay Science (1882) announced a cultural watershed moment in which traditional religious and metaphysical foundations for meaning and morality had crumbled, leaving humanity to confront a universe without inherent purpose or divine guidance. For Nietzsche, this collapse of absolute values represented both a crisis and an opportunity—a chance for humanity to move beyond what he saw as life-denying Christian morality toward life-affirming values based on the affirmation of existence itself.

Nietzsche's concept of the "will to power" offers an alternative framework for understanding human motivation and the creation of meaning. Rather than seeking happiness or pleasure, Nietzsche argued that humans fundamentally desire power—not necessarily power over others, but the expansion of one's capacities and overcoming of resistance. This will to power is not merely a psychological drive but a fundamental principle of life itself, manifested in the striving of all living beings to extend their influence and overcome obstacles. Through the will to power, individuals might create their own values in a world without transcendent sources of meaning.

In Thus Spoke Zarathustra (1883-1885), Nietzsche introduces the ideal of the Übermensch (often translated as "overman" or "superman"), who represents the possibility of overcoming nihilism by affirming life in all its suffering and joy. The Übermensch creates values that affirm life rather than deny it, embracing the concept of "eternal recurrence"—the hypothetical idea that one's life will repeat infinitely—as a test of one's attitude toward existence. To affirm eternal recurrence is to say yes to life in its entirety, with all its pain and pleasure, embracing one's fate (amor fati) rather than wishing for a different reality.

Nietzsche's understanding of suffering differs markedly from traditional Christian views. Rather than viewing suffering as punishment or as something to be endured for future reward, Nietzsche sees suffering as an essential part of growth and self-overcoming. "What does not kill me makes me stronger," he famously wrote, suggesting that overcoming resistance and pain is integral to developing one's capacities. Authenticity, for Nietzsche, lies in embracing one's nature, creating life-affirming values, and living in accordance with them despite social pressure to conform to conventional morality.

Nietzsche's critique of morality as a system of control, his emphasis on individual value-creation, and his insistence on affirming life in the face of meaninglessness laid crucial groundwork for later existentialist thinkers, who would further develop his insights about freedom, responsibility, and authentic existence in a world without given meaning.

Søren Kierkegaard: The Father of Existentialism

Søren Kierkegaard (1813-1855), often regarded as the father of existentialism, predated the formal movement but established many of its central concerns. Writing in 19th century Denmark, Kierkegaard developed a philosophical approach that emphasized the individual's subjective relationship to truth, the importance of choice, and the necessity of faith in the face of uncertainty. Unlike systematic philosophers who sought to construct comprehensive rational frameworks, Kierkegaard focused on the lived experience of the individual confronting life's fundamental questions.

For Kierkegaard, truth is subjectivity—not in the sense that objective reality doesn't exist, but that what matters most is how the individual relates to truth. In Concluding Unscientific Postscript (1846), he writes, "Subjectivity is truth," emphasizing that the passionate inward appropriation of belief is more significant than abstract, detached speculation. This prioritization of subjective engagement over objective detachment would become a hallmark of existentialist thought.

Kierkegaard outlined three stages of existence: the aesthetic, the ethical, and the religious. The aesthetic stage is characterized by pursuit of pleasure and immediate gratification, living in the moment without commitment. The ethical stage involves commitment to universal moral principles and social responsibilities. The religious stage represents the highest form of existence, where the individual makes a "leap of faith" beyond rational understanding, exemplified by Abraham's willingness to sacrifice Isaac in Kierkegaard's Fear and Trembling (1843). This leap involves a "teleological suspension of the ethical"—going beyond universal ethical norms through faith in one's particular relationship with the divine.

Central to Kierkegaard's philosophy is the concept of anxiety (Angest), which he explores in The Concept of Anxiety(1844). Anxiety arises from the awareness of freedom and possibility—the dizzying recognition that one must choose without certainty of outcomes. This anxiety is not merely a psychological state but an ontological condition that reveals fundamental truths about human existence. Through anxiety, we confront our freedom and the responsibility it entails.

Kierkegaard's understanding of suffering is deeply influenced by his Christian faith. He saw suffering not as something to be avoided but as potentially redemptive, a means of deepening one's inward life and relationship with God. In Works of Love (1847) and other writings, he emphasizes that authentic Christian love involves suffering for the sake of others, following Christ's example of self-sacrifice. Yet Kierkegaard's view of suffering is not masochistic; rather, it recognizes suffering as an inevitable part of deeper commitment and authentic existence.

Authenticity, for Kierkegaard, means living in accordance with one's highest values and commitments rather than conforming to social expectations or abstract philosophical systems. He was deeply critical of "Christendom"—the nominal, cultural Christianity of his time—which he saw as inauthentic. True faith, he argued, requires passionate commitment in the face of uncertainty, not comfortable adherence to established doctrines or social conventions. This emphasis on passionate commitment to one's own truth would significantly influence later existentialist thought, even among thinkers who rejected Kierkegaard's religious framework.

Arthur Schopenhauer: The Will to Live and the Problem of Suffering

Arthur Schopenhauer (1788-1860), while not typically classified as an existentialist, developed philosophical ideas that significantly influenced existentialist thought, particularly in his analysis of human will, suffering, and the search for meaning. His magnum opus, The World as Will and Representation (1818), presents a metaphysical system that resonates with existentialist concerns about the human condition and the problem of existence.

Central to Schopenhauer's philosophy is the concept of the "will to live"—a blind, irrational force that drives all living beings. Unlike Kant's noumenal realm, which remains entirely unknowable, Schopenhauer claimed that we can know the thing-in-itself through our direct experience of our own will. The will to live is insatiable, constantly generating new desires once old ones are satisfied, resulting in a cycle of striving, temporary satisfaction, boredom, and renewed striving. This endless cycle is the source of human suffering, as Schopenhauer famously stated: "Life swings like a pendulum backward and forward between pain and boredom."

Schopenhauer's pessimistic assessment of life contradicts the optimism of many Enlightenment thinkers. He argues that suffering is not merely incidental to human existence but intrinsic to it—an inevitable consequence of being driven by will in a world where complete and lasting satisfaction is impossible. "Life is a business that does not cover the costs," he wrote, suggesting that suffering outweighs happiness in human experience. This unflinching acknowledgment of life's inherent suffering would later influence existentialist thinkers, particularly in their rejection of facile optimism and their willingness to confront the darker aspects of human existence.

Despite his pessimism, Schopenhauer offered paths toward alleviating suffering. One approach is through aesthetic contemplation—moments of detached appreciation of art, music, and nature that temporarily free us from the demands of the will. More profound is his ethical approach, which advocates compassion based on recognizing that the same will animates all beings, making their suffering essentially one's own. Finally, Schopenhauer suggests that asceticism—the denial of the will through renunciation of desires—might lead to a state resembling the Buddhist concept of nirvana, where one is freed from the cycle of suffering.

Schopenhauer's understanding of authenticity differs from later existentialists. Rather than emphasizing authentic self-creation through choice, he suggests that authenticity lies in seeing through the illusion of individuality to recognize the universal will that underlies all existence. This recognition leads not to self-assertion but to compassion and renunciation.

While Schopenhauer's metaphysical system and his recommendations for transcending the will diverge from existentialist emphases on freedom and self-creation, his unflinching analysis of suffering, his critique of facile optimism, and his recognition of the problematic nature of human existence establish him as an important predecessor to existentialist thought. His influence is particularly evident in Nietzsche, who, despite rejecting Schopenhauer's pessimism and recommendation of will-denial, built upon his insights about the centrality of will in human life.

Martin Heidegger: Being-in-the-World and Authentic Existence

Martin Heidegger (1889-1976), though rejecting the existentialist label, profoundly influenced existentialist thought through his phenomenological ontology, particularly in his magnum opus Being and Time (1927). Heidegger sought to reawaken the "question of Being" (Seinsfrage), which he believed had been forgotten in Western philosophy since the pre-Socratics. Rather than beginning with abstract metaphysical categories, Heidegger analyzed human existence—which he termed "Dasein" (literally "being-there")—as the entity for whom Being is an issue.

Heidegger's concept of "Being-in-the-world" (In-der-Welt-sein) represents a radical departure from the Cartesian subject-object dualism that had dominated modern philosophy. Dasein is not a detached consciousness observing an external world but is always already engaged in a world of practical concerns, social relations, and cultural meanings. We primarily encounter entities as "ready-to-hand" (zuhanden)—as tools or equipment integrated into our practical activities—rather than as "present-at-hand" (vorhanden) objects of theoretical contemplation. This emphasis on practical engagement over theoretical detachment influenced existentialist approaches to human existence.

In Being and Time, Heidegger analyzes various structures of Dasein's existence, including "care" (Sorge), "thrownness" (Geworfenheit), and "fallenness" (Verfallen). Dasein is "thrown" into a world not of its choosing, with a particular historical, cultural, and personal situation that conditions its possibilities. Dasein is typically "fallen" into inauthentic existence, absorbed in everyday concerns and understanding itself in terms of socially prescribed roles and possibilities rather than confronting its own Being.

Authenticity (Eigentlichkeit), for Heidegger, involves owning one's existence rather than passively accepting social definitions. This becomes possible through anxiety (Angst), which reveals the contingency of social meanings and confronts Dasein with its own freedom and finitude. Most profoundly, authenticity involves anticipatory resoluteness toward death (Vorlaufen zum Tode)—acknowledging mortality not as a distant event but as a defining possibility that individualizes Dasein and gives meaning to its choices. By embracing mortality, Dasein can live authentically, choosing its possibilities in light of its finite temporal existence.

Heidegger's analysis of "Being-toward-death" (Sein-zum-Tode) represents one of his most significant contributions to existentialist thought. Death is not merely the end of life but the possibility of the impossibility of existence—a possibility that reveals the finitude of all other possibilities. Authentic Being-toward-death involves neither fleeing from death nor morbidly obsessing over it, but integrating awareness of mortality into one's understanding of life, allowing for more authentic choices.

The concept of "the they" (das Man) in Being and Time identifies the anonymous social authority that prescribes conventional ways of understanding and acting. Inauthentic Dasein understands itself in terms of what "one" does, thinks, or feels, rather than taking responsibility for its own existence. Authenticity requires breaking free from the tyranny of "the they" to take ownership of one's possibilities, though Heidegger recognizes that Dasein cannot entirely escape its social and historical conditioning.

While Heidegger's later work took a "turn" (Kehre) away from the existential analytics of Dasein toward more poetic meditations on technology, language, and the history of Being, his early analyses in Being and Time provided existentialist philosophy with powerful concepts for understanding human existence as finite, situated, and capable of both authenticity and inauthenticity. His phenomenological method and his emphasis on concrete, lived experience rather than abstract theorizing also significantly influenced existentialist approaches to philosophical problems.

Jean-Paul Sartre: Radical Freedom and the Burden of Responsibility

Jean-Paul Sartre (1905-1980), the most prominent philosopher identified with existentialism, developed a systematic existentialist philosophy that emphasized radical freedom, the absence of predetermined human nature, and the responsibility that comes with creating one's essence through choice. In his philosophical treatise Being and Nothingness (1943) and through literary works like Nausea (1938) and plays such as No Exit (1944), Sartre articulated a vision of human existence characterized by inescapable freedom and the anguish it entails.

Central to Sartre's philosophy is the distinction between being-in-itself (être-en-soi) and being-for-itself (être-pour-soi). Being-in-itself characterizes non-conscious objects, which simply are what they are, without possibility or lack. Being-for-itself describes human consciousness, which is defined by nothingness—the ability to negate what is and envision what is not. Through this negativity, consciousness transcends deterministic causality and creates a space of freedom. As Sartre famously declared, "We are condemned to be free": freedom is not an achievement but an inescapable condition of human existence.

Sartre's dictum that "existence precedes essence" represents the core of his existentialism. Unlike a paper knife, which is created according to a predetermined concept to fulfill a specific function, humans exist first and then define their essence through their choices and actions. There is no human nature, no God-given purpose, no predetermined path—only the meanings and values that individuals create through their free choices. This radical responsibility can produce "anguish," the discomforting awareness that one's choices define not only oneself but implicitly suggest what humanity should be.

Authenticity, for Sartre, involves recognizing and accepting one's radical freedom rather than engaging in "bad faith" (mauvaise foi). Bad faith is self-deception, attempting to escape responsibility by claiming one is determined by external factors—social roles, psychological drives, past events—or, conversely, denying one's facticity by pretending to be unconstrained by physical or social realities. The famous example of the café waiter who performs his role too perfectly illustrates bad faith: he treats his contingent social role as if it were his intrinsic nature, thereby evading responsibility for freely choosing how to be a waiter.

Sartre's understanding of human relations is notably pessimistic. In interactions with others, the "Look" (le regard) of the other objectifies one, threatening one's freedom and subjectivity. Being seen by another person transforms one from a free subject into an object with fixed characteristics. This leads to fundamental conflict in human relationships, as each consciousness seeks to preserve its freedom by objectifying the other. "Hell is other people," declares a character in No Exit, expressing this conflict between consciousnesses.

Despite this pessimism about interpersonal relations, Sartre's later work, particularly Critique of Dialectical Reason(1960), attempted to reconcile existential freedom with Marxist historical materialism, seeking a basis for solidarity and collective action. His concept of "engaged literature" also emphasized that intellectual work should be committed to social and political causes, reflecting his view that freedom must be exercised responsibly within concrete historical situations.

Sartre's analysis of meaning in an apparently meaningless world emphasizes human responsibility for value-creation. Since there is no predetermined meaning to human existence, individuals must create meaning through their projects and commitments. Meaning is not discovered but made, and the authentic individual takes responsibility for the values implied by their choices rather than appealing to external authorities or universal principles. This responsibility extends beyond individual concerns to encompass a vision of what humanity should be, since in choosing for oneself, one implicitly chooses for all.

Albert Camus: Confronting the Absurd

Albert Camus (1913-1960), often associated with existentialism despite his reluctance to accept the label, focused his philosophical work on what he termed "the absurd"—the confrontation between the human desire for meaning and clarity and the silent, indifferent universe. In works such as The Myth of Sisyphus (1942), The Stranger (1942), and The Rebel (1951), Camus explored how humans might live authentically and ethically in a world without inherent meaning or transcendent values.

Camus's philosophical starting point is the recognition of the absurd. "There is only one truly serious philosophical problem," he famously wrote in The Myth of Sisyphus, "and that is suicide. Judging whether life is or is not worth living amounts to answering the fundamental question of philosophy." The absurd arises not from the universe itself but from the confrontation between human reason, which seeks order and meaning, and an irrational world that offers neither. This recognition might lead to despair, but Camus rejects suicide as a solution, arguing that it merely eliminates one term of the absurd equation (the human consciousness) without resolving the confrontation.

Camus also rejects what he calls "philosophical suicide"—attempts to escape the absurd through appeals to transcendent meaning, whether religious (like Kierkegaard's leap of faith) or secular (like Heidegger's Being or Husserl's essences). Such leaps, Camus argues, evade rather than confront the absurd. Instead, he advocates maintaining what he calls "absurd reasoning," which acknowledges the human desire for meaning while refusing to deny the world's indifference or to fabricate false consolations.

The myth of Sisyphus—condemned by the gods to eternally roll a boulder up a mountain, only to have it roll back down—becomes Camus's metaphor for the human condition. Like Sisyphus, humans engage in apparently meaningless tasks in a world indifferent to their efforts. Yet Camus concludes, "One must imagine Sisyphus happy." This counterintuitive claim suggests that meaning can be found in the act of confronting the absurd with clear-eyed awareness. Sisyphus's consciousness of his fate, his scorn for the gods, and his passionate engagement with his task constitute a victory despite his eternal punishment.

This leads to Camus's understanding of rebellion as an essential response to the absurd. In The Rebel, he distinguishes between metaphysical rebellion (against the human condition) and historical rebellion (against specific social and political injustices). Authentic rebellion says both "no" to oppression and absurdity and "yes" to certain values that transcend the individual. Unlike nihilistic revolution, which justifies any means by appeal to future ends, genuine rebellion respects limits and affirms common human dignity even while challenging existing conditions.

Camus's ethic of quantity suggests that in the absence of eternal values, one should seek to live as intensely and fully as possible, embracing experiences rather than deferring life for future rewards. However, this is not mere hedonism, as Camus emphasizes that genuine rebellion involves solidarity with others and commitment to justice. His concept of "the absurd man" evolves into "the man in revolt," who recognizes that authentic existence requires not only personal lucidity but also commitment to others.

Suffering, for Camus, is an inevitable aspect of human existence, not a punishment or a means to spiritual growth but simply a fact of life in an indifferent universe. The plague in his novel The Plague (1947) symbolizes the arbitrary suffering that humans must confront together. Dr. Rieux, the novel's protagonist, exemplifies Camus's ideal response: neither denying suffering's reality nor attributing transcendent meaning to it, but working tirelessly to alleviate it while acknowledging its inevitability.

Authenticity, in Camus's view, involves refusing both despair and false hope, maintaining lucid awareness of the absurd while passionately engaging in life and affirming common human values. Unlike some existentialists, Camus emphasizes that authentic existence must include solidarity with others, not merely individual self-creation. His later work increasingly focused on themes of moderation, limits, and the Mediterranean values of beauty, sensuality, and human fellowship as counterweights to ideological fanaticism and despair.

Conclusion: Existentialism's Enduring Relevance

The existentialist tradition, from its roots in Kierkegaard and Nietzsche through its full articulation in thinkers like Heidegger, Sartre, and Camus, offers profound insights that remain relevant to contemporary life. In an age characterized by rapid technological change, fragmentation of traditional communities, environmental crisis, and political polarization, existentialist emphases on freedom, responsibility, authenticity, and meaning-creation provide valuable resources for navigating personal and collective challenges.

The existentialist critique of mass society and conformity speaks directly to contemporary concerns about social media's homogenizing effects, algorithmic determination of experience, and the substitution of virtual connection for genuine encounter. Heidegger's analysis of "the they" and Sartre's concept of "bad faith" offer tools for recognizing and resisting these tendencies, encouraging critical reflection on how digital technologies shape identities and relationships. Similarly, Camus's warning against ideological fanaticism and his emphasis on moderation and human solidarity provide antidotes to the polarization and tribalism that characterize much contemporary political discourse.

In a secular age where traditional religious frameworks no longer command widespread assent, the existentialist approach to meaning-creation offers alternatives to both nihilism and uncritical consumption. Rather than seeing the absence of given meaning as a cause for despair, existentialist thinkers suggest that it opens possibilities for authentic creation of values and purposes. This perspective is particularly valuable in addressing contemporary crises of meaning and purpose, which manifest in rising rates of depression, anxiety, and addiction. The existentialist emphasis on confronting rather than evading life's difficulties challenges therapeutic cultures that sometimes prioritize comfort over growth and authenticity.

Environmental crisis, perhaps the defining challenge of our time, can be approached through an existentialist lens that emphasizes responsibility for choices that affect not only current humans but future generations and other species. While existentialism is often characterized as anthropocentric, its insights about finitude, interconnection, and responsibility can be extended to encompass ecological concerns. The existentialist rejection of both determinism and naive optimism encourages clear-eyed assessment of environmental realities while maintaining commitment to meaningful action despite uncertain outcomes.

The existentialist treatment of suffering offers resources for confronting both personal and collective suffering without resorting to either despair or denial. Nietzsche's concept of amor fati (love of fate), Schopenhauer's emphasis on compassion, and Camus's ethic of solidarity in the face of absurdity provide alternatives to a culture that often oscillates between false positivity and nihilistic resignation. By acknowledging suffering as an inevitable aspect of existence while maintaining commitment to alleviating unnecessary suffering, existentialist approaches avoid both sentimentality and cynicism.

Critics have rightly noted existentialism's limitations, including tendencies toward excessive individualism, privileging of male experience, Eurocentrism, and occasional political naivete. However, these limitations reflect its historical context rather than inherent flaws in its core insights. Contemporary engagements with existentialist thought can address these limitations by bringing existentialist concepts into dialogue with feminist, decolonial, and ecological perspectives, expanding rather than abandoning its valuable contributions.

The existentialist emphasis on embodied, situated existence—most fully developed in phenomenological existentialism—challenges both disembodied rationalism and digital disembodiment. In an age increasingly dominated by virtual experience and artificial intelligence, the existentialist insistence on the irreducibility of embodied human experience offers important correctives to posthumanist fantasies and technological solutionism. Heidegger's critique of technology as a "revealing" that reduces beings to resources, Merleau-Ponty's phenomenology of the body, and Sartre's analysis of the Look all provide resources for critical engagement with technological developments that might otherwise proceed without adequate philosophical reflection.

Finally, existentialism's emphasis on authenticity remains relevant in contemporary contexts where authenticity is simultaneously valorized and commodified. From corporate initiatives promoting "authentic leadership" to social media performances of "authentic living," contemporary culture often reduces authenticity to a brand or aesthetic rather than a demanding existential achievement. Existentialist thinkers remind us that authenticity involves confronting uncomfortable truths about freedom, finitude, and responsibility rather than conforming to cultural scripts about "being yourself." This critical perspective on authenticity provides resources for resisting both conformity masquerading as individuality and narcissistic self-absorption disguised as self-realization.

In conclusion, while existentialism emerged in specific historical contexts and reflects particular cultural preoccupations, its fundamental insights about human existence transcend those contexts. By focusing on concrete human experience rather than abstract metaphysical systems, existentialist thinkers developed approaches to freedom, meaning, suffering, and authenticity that remain relevant across cultural and historical boundaries. In a world characterized by rapid change, environmental crisis, technological transformation, and social fragmentation, existentialist perspectives offer valuable resources for navigating personal and collective challenges with courage, clarity, and commitment to human dignity. The existentialist tradition reminds us that even in the absence of given meanings or purposes, humans can create lives of authenticity, responsibility, and solidarity through their choices and commitments.